Woollin: more on foresight and all that

AuthorC. G. Hall
PositionOf the Faculty of Law, University of the West Indies, Cave Hill Campus, Barbados
Pages93-112
WOOLLIN: MORE ON FORESIGHT
AND
ALL
THAT
C. G. HALL*
Things are seldom as they seem. In Woollin,1 the House of Lords considered
once again the mental element in murder. The leading speech was delivered by
Lord Steyn. As a consequence, there seems little doubt that Woollin will be
perceived as a 'landmark' decision in the manner of
D.P.P.
v. Smith2 and Hyam v.
D.P.P.3 For, on one analysis, what Woollin has done is to compound the errors
bedeviling the mens red of murder for nearly four decades; this since Lord Steyn,
with the dexterity of those with great creative power, ingenuously, unaffectedly and
imaginatively contrived to re-write two House of Lords and a larger number of
Court of Appeal decisions in the name of consistency and orthodoxy. Yet,
paradoxically, in doing so, and perhaps despite that artistry, the Noble and Learned
Lord arguably re-set the foundations of the mental element in murder as judicially
understood on a surer footing.
It is unnecessary to rehearse Smith and Hyam. Each contained erroneous
expositions of law. Leaving aside the effect of s.8 of the Criminal Justice Act, 1967
in England,4 at common law the presumption
that
a man intends the natural and
probable consequences of his actions is of evidential significance
only
and is to be
accounted with all other evidence to test D's subjective
state
of mind.5 Similarly,
for D to do an unlawful act with knowledge that death or grievous bodily harm is
Of the Faculty of Law, University of the West Indies, Cave Hill Campus, Barbados.
1 [1998] 4 All E.R. 103.
2 [1961] 3 All E.R. 161.
3 [1974] 2 All
E.R.
41.
4 In the Commonwealth Caribbean, see, e.g., s.9, Belize Criminal Code, Cap. 84; s.7(4),
Montserrat Penal Code, No. 12 of
1983,
s.28 Bermuda Evidence Act, Title 8 Item 10.
5 See,
e.g.,
Hyam [19741 2 All E.R,
41,
at p. 52 fur Lord Hailsham; Moloney [1985]
1
All E.R
1025,
at p. 1033 per Lord Bridge;
Hancock
[1986] 1 All E.R. 641, at pp. 649-50 per Lord
Scarman; Frankland [1987] A.C 576
(P.C.);
Johnson (1966-67) 10 W.I.R. 402; Reid (1978)
32 W.I.R. 77. But cf. Code provisions in the Commonwealth Caribbean; s. 72, St. Lucia
Criminal Code 1992; s. 11(3), The Bahamas Penal Code, Ch. 77; s.12(3), Grenada Criminal
Code, Cap. 76, See, however, Tench (1991) 41 W.I.R, 103; Samson St. Lucia (unrep.) No.l
of
1989
(25.10.93).
a highly probable consequence of that act is not the same as an intention to do the
act but only evidential of
his
intention to do it.6
Yet in theory and practice this is not the end of the matter. For example, on
the question of foresight, does a man who foresees a result as an inevitable
consequence of what he set out to achieve in law intend that result? Is there a
point in the range of foreseen probabilities - less or more likely than not, likely,
probable, highly probable, very highly probable, virtually certain - below which
foresight is evidentially irrelevant? Or may any level of foresight be taken into the
profile? These and other things were explored, at times incompletely and
incoherently, in the speech of Lord Bridge in Moloney7 and in later cases8 serving
essentially as commentaries on that decision. Thus it is
Moloney
which is critical
to the discussion. What did it decide?
Until Lord Steyn's speech in Woollin, the present writer had no doubt that
Moloney decided rwn things: first, that the
mens
rea of murder is the specific intent
to kill or cause grievous bodily harm and nothing
else;
secondly, that D's foresight
of death or grievous bodily harm is no more than evidence of those intentions,
albeit that in an appropriate case it might prove critical if the level of foreseen
probability
was
sufficiently high.9 However, to Lord
Bridge,
who delivered the main
speech and with whom all other Lords of Appeal expressed agreement, there was
one case where a foreseen result was to be classified
as
intentional. This was where
D foresaw the result as a "moral certainty"10 or, in ordinary language, as inevitable,
as in the hypothetical example he gave of the man who boards a plane at London
Airport bound for Manchescer solely to escape pursuit- The man has no desire to
travel to Manchester for its own sake but "conclusively demonstrates his intention
to go there, because it is a moral certainty that is where he will arrive."11 In other
situations, cases prior to Moloney had suggested that "the probability of the
consequence taken to have been foreseen must be little short of overwhelming
6 Moloney [1985]
1
All E
.R.
1025. But in the Commonwealth Caribbean cf., e.g.,
s.71,
St. Lucia
Criminal Code 1992; s. 11(2), The Bahamas Penal Code, Ch,
77;
s.12(2), Grenada Criminal
Code, Cap. 76.
7 Supra, n. 6.
8 Hancock [1986] 1 All
E.R.
641;
Nedrick
[1986] 3
All E.R.
1;
Barr (1989) 88 Cr. App, R. 362;
Walker * Hayles (1990) 90 Cr. App. R
226;
and
Woollin
[1997]
1
Cr. App R. 97 (C.A.).
9 Seemingly, these were the answers to the two certified questions of the Court of Appeal (see
per Lord Bridge at p. 1029), assuming thai the reference to foresight of probability in the
second question covers the entire range of foreseen probabilities other than, foreseen "moral
certainty".
10 At
p.
1037- The phrase seems to be derived from Lord Hailsham's speech in Hyam: [1974] 2
All
E.R.
41,
at p. 52.
11 Ibid.

To continue reading

Request your trial

VLEX uses login cookies to provide you with a better browsing experience. If you click on 'Accept' or continue browsing this site we consider that you accept our cookie policy. ACCEPT